123456789101112131415161718192021222324252627282930313233343536373839404142434445464748495051525354555657585960616263646566676869707172737475767778798081828384858687888990919293 |
- The Meno asks the question “what is virtue and can it be taught?”. Meno’s conversation with Socrates is an
- attempt to know exactly what virtue means and how it can be defined to come to the decision of whether or not it
- can in fact be taught to others. But as Meno finds, contrary to his original perceptions as an ethical relativist, he
- does not know what virtue is, and in his new state of ethical absolutism, cannot therefore teach Socrates what
- virtue is, for how can one teach what one does not know? It becomes the conclusion amongst the two, that virtue is
- a divine gift to those who are virtuous, and cannot be taught as it is not knowledge and it cannot be said that there
- are teachers of it. However, Socrates, through his refutations of Meno’s questions and arguments, does not justify
- his conclusion that it cannot be taught.
- Several logical fallacies are present within the argument put forth by Socrates. And as Meno states, he
- has a numbing effect on those around him, such that they might not even notice his failings until a later
- examination.
- After exhausting all definitions he has for what virtue is, all of them being countered by Socrates and
- determined to be inadequate definitions, one of the problem’s Meno then has with understanding what virtue is
- comes from this paradox: How can you try to find out something, when you have no notion at all about what it is?
- However, the problem Meno has here is not clearly stated. Does he suggest that you either know what you’re
- looking for, and therefore do not need to inquire into it, or you don’t know what you’re looking for, and therefore
- cannot inquire into it, because you don’t know it? This leads to the question of whether what you know is either
- the question you want to ask, or the answer to that question. One obviously cannot both know and not know the
- same thing. However, one can know the question but not the answer. Therefore, you can inquire into something
- you do not know of, if you know the question you wish to ask. And from this question, you would follow whatever
- steps are necessary to get the answer, and end up knowing which you did not previously know. However, Socrates
- puts forth a different perspective here, by attempting to demonstrate his Recollection Theory. This theory purports
- that inquiry can be impossible in some instances, but what is seen to be learning is in fact the recollection of
- something previously known.
- Though Socrates puts forth an admirable effort to support his recollection theory, there is a flaw in his
- argument. He uses a slave boy to exemplify how the theory works. He sets forth the geometrical problem to the
- slave boy simply enough; however, with each wrong answer from the boy, he proceeds to lead him closer to the
- correct conclusion. The boy makes guesses, that Socrates dismisses in small conversation bits with Meno to one
- side. Right away, this would suggest that he is, in fact, teaching the boy something, whether he will admit to it or
- not. When the boy suggests the length of the lines be doubled to four to make a square of eight, Socrates
- immediately speaks with Meno and asks if he is correct , to which Meno replies that the boy is wrong in his
- assumption. Socrates draws this new square and specifically asks “Is four times the old one double?” to which the
- boy replies no, it is four times. This information was given to him by Socrates. After the boy unsuccessfully tries
- to determine the answer to Socrates’ puzzle again by saying that the line should now be three, Socrates gives the
- boy the answer by drawing lines bm, mi, ig, gb (top of page forty-nine) and asking him if that is not the answer, to
- which the boy replies in the affirmative. It is almost puzzling as to why Meno agrees with Socrates that the boy
- simply answered the question on his own, when he so obviously did not. It could be speculated that given the
- stature of Socrates at the time, Meno simply couldn’t bring himself to disagree, or was so sure of Socrates’ wisdom,
- that he accepted his example as truth. Had it not been for the help of Socrates, the boy might never have known
- the answer. As well, there is the possibility that, in this situation, the act of reasoning could take place. Whereby
- the slave boy could have simply deduced the correct answer, having seen the consequences of his previous answers.
- This counters the recollection theory as it provides the individual with new knowledge that is based around old, but
- not recalled from some distant past memory.
- Given that the answer was provided by Socrates, it does not lend any credence to his theory of
- recollection. As such, it could not be said that virtue is an unteachable thing, at least not by this example, for he
- has not proven that all knowledge is merely recollection. As well, there are a good number of alternate instances
- when such an argument cannot be made. Aside from instances where one might reason a new answer, such can be
- said for empirical knowledge, with a question like “how many quarters are in my pocket?”. Determining the
- answer to that will give you knowledge you did not previously have, and could not previously have. In effect, after
- you count the quarters, you will have learned something new. As such, all knowledge is clearly not recollection.
- Proceeding with the conversation between Meno and Socrates, the answer as to what virtue is has yet to be
- found. And Meno at this point wishes to know if it is something that can be taught or attained by other means.
- Socrates allows that they do not yet even know what virtue is, but ventures to determine whether it be learned or
- not. Through a conversation with Antyos, whereby Socrates points out that the fine men of the region are known to
- pay others in the teachings of their sons in things which are good, it is established that neither the Sophists nor
- well bred, fine gentleman are teachers of virtue. For if they were, surely they would pass this virtue onto their sons
- and have no need of paying others in their educations. And if it is clear there are no other teachers of virtue, and
- therefore no learners, then virtue cannot be taught at all, and is not knowledge. However, Socrates has trapped
- himself here, in a way. For Meno, at the beginning of the discussion, was sure in his knowledge of virtue. His
- false opinion was then exposed by Socrates, and throughout the conversation he has become enlightened. Socrates
- has taught Meno what virtue is not. Knowing what virtue is not will bring Meno closer to knowing what it is, in a
- kind of backward way. Certainly, it cannot be said that Meno has discovered virtue, but he is one step closer. And
- one cannot know X, if one does not know that X is not Y. By the same token, Meno cannot know what virtue is, if
- he does not know what virtue is not. So Meno has learned something of virtue that he did not previously know.
- The Meno progresses as it does, due in no small part because Meno himself is poor at what he does. He
- asks Socrates on several occasions for answers, “what do you say colour is?” and “no, Socrates, but you tell me”
- rather than attempting to formulate ideas of his own. There are occasions when Socrates gives him openings to
- add his own insight and opinions, but he does not take them. After “proving” his theory of recollection, he asks
- Meno many times if the boys opinions were his own and not influenced by Socrates, but Meno simply agrees with
- the opinions presented by Socrates instead of adding anything of his own. He constantly defers to Socrates and
- accepts the answers he receives from him. He does not use inquiry to determine the answers he seeks and as such
- shows that over the course of the dialogue, he has in fact determined nothing, while Socrates has come upon
- everything, making Meno a poor Socratic thinker. Because of this, the strength of the dialogue and the points that
- are made with in seems weakened, as it is less of a dialogue and more of a lesson imparted by Socrates. When it
- becomes clear that Meno is bringing little to the ideas formulated, then the conclusions lose power, from something
- mutually discovered by two thinkers, to ideas formulated by one man and shared with another.
- It is Socrates’ final conclusion that neither he nor Meno has found the true meaning of virtue. It is
- something that the two still must seek to understand. And though he believes he has isolated virtue as something
- which cannot be taught based on his examples, and which is imparted by the divine unto those who are virtuous,
- his reasons for achieving these conclusions can be greatly debated, as they do have many apparent flaws. These
- flaws make it so that the conclusions made by Socrates do not follow logically and as such, his conclusions cannot
- be said to be logical. What Socrates does achieve is in determining that he himself has not come upon a teacher of
- virtue in personal experience, which is certainly not a philosophical discovery and cannot be said to prove his
- point. By the end of his dialogue with Meno, Socrates has enlightened Meno insofar as teaching him that he does
- not, in fact, know the nature of virtue, thus changing his double ignorance to single, from ethical relativism to
- absolutism However, now neither of them can say they know virtue, nor can they conclusively say that virtue can
- be taught, or cannot be taught.
- <br><br><b>Bibliography</b><br><br>
- Plato. “Meno.” Great Dialogues of Plato. Ed. Rouse, Rouse, Warmington. New York: Mentor, 1956. 28-69
- <br><br>
- Words: 1658
|